Category Archives: Uncategorized

Resurrecting the Equal Protection Clause Through the Ku Klux Klan Act of 1871

By: Thomas E. Nielsen*

Introduction

In 1871, the former Confederacy had descended into relentless violence committed by the Ku Klux Klan.1 Murders, lynching, and other acts of brutality were commonplace, and with states unable—or unwilling—to enforce their own laws against the perpetrators, the South was in a state of anarchy. 2

In response, Congress enacted the Ku Klux Klan Act in April of 1871 to enforce various portions of the recently ratified Fourteenth Amendment.3 The law’s most famous provision, section 1 (now codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. § 1983), provided a civil damages remedy for violations of constitutional rights committed “under color of any [state] law . . . [or] custom.”4 Section 2 created civil and criminal liability, inter alia, if “two or more persons . . . go in disguise upon the public highway or upon the premises of another for the purpose . . . of depriving any person or any class of persons of the equal protection of the laws.”5 And section 6 imposed civil liability for anyone who knew of a section 2 conspiracy and was in a position to stop it, but failed to do so.6

The Klan Act was largely forgotten in the decades following its passage,7 especially after the criminal conspiracy component of section 2 was struck down by the Supreme Court in United States v. Harris.8 Nonetheless, in the early 1960s, § 1983 experienced a revival after the Court held in Monroe v. Pape that any unconstitutional action taken by an officer “clothed with the authority of state law” could create damages liability, even if the action itself violated state law.9 As § 1983 became the predominant means by which plaintiffs vindicated their constitutional rights, sections 2 and 6 of the Klan Act, now codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 1985–86, respectively, languished.10 This was partially due to the long shadow cast by Harris,11 and partially due to the Court’s development of the modern state action doctrine,12 which provides that only action attributable to the state,13 or private action that is “pervasive[ly] entwine[d]” with the state,14 can violate the Fourteenth Amendment (and the amendments it incorporates). Applying those principles, the Court reasoned that § 1985’s civil conspiracy provisions could only apply to conspiracies by state actors,15 or the rare private conspiracy that involves a constitutional violation capable of being committed by a nonstate actor.16 That profoundly narrow interpretation rendered § 1985, and by extension § 1986, largely nugatory.17

But the Court’s interpretation of § 1985 raises a quandary: assuming only state actors can enter into a conspiracy to violate the Fourteenth Amendment, how could the same legislators who had drafted that Amendment draft a statute creating liability for private conspiracies entered into “for the purpose of depriving . . . any person or class of persons of the equal protection of the laws” or “preventing or hindering the constituted authorities of any State or Territory from giving or securing to all persons . . . the equal protection of the laws”?18 A close reading of the legislative history of the Klan Act reveals that the Court’s interpretation of § 1985 has, as a historical matter, gone seriously awry, in part because of the Court’s ahistorical interpretation of the Equal Protection Clause itself.19 In fact, the legislative history—as well as early circuit court and Supreme Court opinions interpreting the Equal Protection Clause—reveals that the Klan Act had, in important respects, a much broader reach than the Supreme Court has held.

The moderate Republicans who helped to enact the Fourteenth Amendment believed that in addition to racially discriminatory state laws and law enforcement, the systematic nonenforcement of state law in a manner that facilitated private acts of racial terrorism violated the Equal Protection Clause. These legislators theorized that both types of state action could trigger federal intervention under the Fourteenth Amendment. And they passed the Klan Act to facilitate such intervention. The result was a carefully calibrated statutory scheme covering those two distinct forms of state action. Section 1983 was engineered—and has correctly been interpreted—to provide a remedy against state officials who enforce discriminatory laws or facially neutral laws in a discriminatory manner. Sections 1985–86, conversely, were engineered to guard against the nonenforcement of state law, providing a remedy against (1) anyone who conspired to deprive Black individuals of their life, liberty, or property in the face of chronic failures by state law enforcement; and (2) anyone who allowed such deprivations to occur.

A historically sensitive reading of §§ 1985 and 1986, coupled with the Equal Protection Clause, could have significant advantages for civil rights plaintiffs. Using incarcerated individuals as a case study, this essay—building on important work by Professors Pamela Brandwein20 and Linda Fisher,21 among others—proposes a historical framework under which the Klan Act might be used to remedy inequitable law enforcement. Such a framework is important because Monroe’s gloss on § 1983 has, for some time, been under attack by those who believe it to be a misreading of the Klan Act’s text and history.22 For instance, dissenting in Crawford-El v. Britton, Justice Scalia justified the Court’s notoriously ahistorical qualified immunity jurisprudence as a corrective mechanism for what he perceived to be the equally ahistorical opinion in Monroe.23 More recently, Justice Thomas has critiqued the Court’s approach to qualified immunity while simultaneously questioning the validity of Monroe.24 In light of the Court’s hostility towards its well-established civil rights precedents, an account of the Klan Act’s original public meaning would likely be welcomed by jurists who contend that such meaning sheds light on how Reconstruction-era civil rights statutes should be used today.

This essay proceeds as follows. Part I provides a historical account of how the Equal Protection Clause was understood to protect against systemic state law enforcement failures that facilitated private acts of racial violence. Part II explains how § 1985 and (particularly) § 1986 worked to implement the Clause’s guarantees. Part III offers a brief account of racially motivated25 violence in prisons, discusses how such violence might be remedied (or not) under current civil rights law, then explains how the historical framework set forth in Part II could help incarcerated plaintiffs vindicate their equal protection rights.

I. The Nonenforcement of State Law as an Equal Protection Violation

It is hornbook constitutional law that the Equal Protection Clause forbids facially discriminatory laws,26 as well as the discriminatory enforcement of facially neutral laws.27 But the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment also viewed the Equal Protection Clause as a guarantee that states would not willfully or negligently refuse to enforce their laws with respect to acts of terrorism committed against Black people. As Professors Randy Barnett and Evan Bernick explain, the text of the Clause “expressed a concept of equal protection . . . according to which state inaction could constitute a denial of protection, and Republicans consistently expressed this understanding” at the time of enactment.28

In the wake of the Civil War, Southern states routinely and pervasively failed to enforce their criminal laws with respect to vigilante violence by the Ku Klux Klan against freedmen:

Klan violence was often election-related though Klansmen also brutalized blacks who made good wages in railroad construction, driving them back to farming, where earnings were significantly lower. The failure of state authorities to protect blacks . . . was widespread. Eyewitness accounts “confirmed again and again the enormity of the problem and the complete failure of the state governments (sic) to restore order.”29

The legislators who drafted the Fourteenth Amendment believed that a state’s failure to protect its Black citizens from Klan violence triggered Congress’s power to provide a federal remedy.30 But unlike discriminatory law enforcement and adjudication, this notion—that the systemic nonenforcement of laws with respect to racial violence can constitute an equal protection violation—has largely been lost to history.31

As Brandwein exhaustively shows in her book-length study of the subject,32 early cases at both the circuit court and Supreme Court levels support the notion that the Equal Protection Clause guarded against the chronic nonenforcement (or underenforcement) of state law. For example, Judge (and future Justice) William Woods wrote in United States v. Hall that “[d]enying includes inaction as well as action, and denying the equal protection of the laws includes the omission to protect, as well as the omission to pass laws for protection.”33 Justice Joseph Bradley, sitting as circuit justice, further developed a theory of state nonenforcement in United States v. Cruikshank, explaining that Congress could remedy “murders, robberies, assaults, thefts, and offenses” if “the state should deny to [Black] persons . . . the equal protection of the laws.”34

Chief Justice Morrison Waite adopted this theory in an opinion for the Supreme Court upholding Justice Bradley’s Cruikshank ruling, writing that “[e]very republican government is in duty bound to protect all its citizens in the enjoyment of [equal protection],” and that the “obligation resting upon the United States is to see that the States do not deny the right.”35 Finally, in the Civil Rights Cases, Justice Bradley again espoused a view of equal protection that encompassed both unequal enforcement and nonenforcement, writing that “civil rights . . . cannot be impaired by the wrongful acts of individuals, unsupported by state authority.36 This language, which speaks in terms of state “support” as opposed to affirmative state action, stands for the principle that “a state can deny rights by shielding, excusing, or protecting individual race-based wrongs” as well as by engaging in discriminatory law execution and adjudication.37

As a matter of original understanding, then, the Equal Protection Clause empowered Congress to legislate pursuant to the Equal Protection Clause to remedy life, liberty, and property deprivations arising from: (1) racially discriminatory state laws or law enforcement; and (2) private acts of racial violence tacitly permitted to go unpunished by states’ willful or negligent failure to enforce their laws against the perpetrators.38

II. Remedying Nonenforcement Under 42 U.S.C. §§ 1985 and 1986.

Section 1 of the Klan Act, now codified as § 1983, was understood by its framers to permit civil rights plaintiffs to vindicate their right to be free from racially discriminatory state laws or law enforcement39—and remains so understood today.40 But the Klan Act also contained provisions—specifically, sections 2 and 6—geared at allowing plaintiffs to vindicate their right to be free of private acts of racial violence facilitated by chronic failures in state law enforcement.

A. The Scope of Sections 2 and 6.

Sections 2 and 6 of the Klan Act, now codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 1985 and 1986, targeted anyone who committed racially motivated violence with impunity due to the “breakdown of law enforcement in the southern states.”41 Section 2 was “packed with provisions,”42 but for present purposes, the relevant language created criminal or civil liability:

if two or more persons . . . shall conspire together, or go in disguise upon the public highway or upon the premises of another for the purpose, either directly or indirectly, of depriving any person or any class of persons of the equal protection of the laws . . . or for the purpose of preventing or hindering the constituted authorities of any State from giving or securing to all persons within such State the equal protection of the laws . . . [and] one or more persons engaged in any such conspiracy shall do, or cause to be done, any act in furtherance of the object of such conspiracy.43

Section 6, in turn, created a civil damages remedy for the failure to stop a section 2 conspiracy, providing:

[t]hat [if] any person or persons, having knowledge that any of the wrongs conspired to be done and mentioned in the second section of this act are about to be committed, and having power to prevent or aid in preventing the same, shall neglect or refuse so to do, and such wrongful act shall be committed, such person or persons shall be liable to the person injured44

Although some radical Republican legislators appear to have viewed the expansive language of sections 2 and 6 as reaching all persons who conspired to commit race-based wrongs, regardless of a state’s nonenforcement,45 the moderates who believed the Equal Protection Clause only allowed the federal government to remedy private racial violence in the wake of state nonenforcement also viewed sections 2 and 6 as the appropriate pathway through which to effectuate such a remedy. For instance, as then-Congressman and future President James A. Garfield—a moderate—explained, discussing section 2’s civil and criminal conspiracy provisions:

[T]he chief complaint is not that the laws of the State are unequal, but that even where the laws are just and equal on their face, yet, by a systematic maladministration of them, or a neglect or refusal to enforce their provisions, a portion of the people are denied equal protection under them. Whenever such a state of facts is clearly made out, [the Equal Protection Clause] . . . empowers Congress to step in and provide for doing justice . . . .46

Considering section 2 to be unconstitutionally overbroad as written, Congressman Garfield then argued that:

if the second section of the pending bill can be so amended that it shall clearly define this offense . . . I shall give it my hearty support. These limitations will not impair the efficiency of the section, but will remove the serious objections that are entertained by many gentlemen to the section as it now stands.47

Congressman Aaron Perry, another moderate, addressed the expansive language of section 2 in a slightly different way: by reading an unwritten state nonenforcement predicate into it. He viewed section 2 as redressing deprivations inflicted by private “conspiracies and unlawful combinations with at least the tacit acquiescence of the State authorities.48 Congressman John Farnsworth similarly described section 2’s conspiracy provisions as reaching private wrongs in cases where the “constituted authorities” were prevented from “being able to afford protection to those persons who constitute a portion of the people.”49 In light of the idea that the Equal Protection Clause itself was triggered only when a state failed to protect its Black citizens from violence, these legislators’ characterization of section 2 makes sense, as private individuals could not conspire to deprive someone of “equal protection” unless there was already a failure to protect by state officials.

Following Congressman Perry and Congressman Farnsworth, it appears that at least a handful of legislators viewed section 2 as constitutional precisely because the provision only reached conspiracies by two or more persons. In other words, the presence of individual acts of vigilante violence, without more, was not a good proxy for a chronic breakdown of state law enforcement. But the presence of unlawful conspiracies suggested a more widespread violence facilitated by systematic inability or refusal by state authorities to tamp down on Klan terrorism. In a revealing exchange between Congressman Farnsworth and the Klan Act’s drafter, Senator Samuel Shellabarger, the latter stated that section 2 “would [not] have the same constitutional qualities if it [applied]” in cases of individual murder, manslaughter, and the like,50 because it was the combination of persons that gave a given act of racial violence the sufficient “magnitude” to constitute an equal protection violation.51 Senator Shellabarger then continued, “if, in case of unlawful combinations, the proper authorities” provided assistance, the Klan Act “would not touch the case at all.”52 This exchange suggests that section 2’s drafter viewed the existence of conspiracies as a sign of state nonenforcement in a way isolated, individual acts of violence were not.

Though there is significantly less discussion of section 6 in the legislative record, Senator Shellabarger told Congressman Garfield that “[section 6] reaches every species of mischief covered by the second section.”53 And the provision’s language—of “neglect or refus[al]”54—mirrors legislators’ characterizations of the what the Equal Protection Clause empowered Congress to remedy. To provide just one example, Congressman Ulysses Mercur explained that “if a State denies . . . equal protection, the United States Government must step in and give that protection which the State authorities neglect or refuse to give.”55 Interpreted in light of the comments by Congressmen Perry and Farnsworth and Senator Shellabarger about section 2, section 6 would have allowed civil damages in cases where states systemically failed to remedy acts of racial terror, against anyone (officials or otherwise) who knew about conspiracies to commit such acts and negligently (or recklessly, or willfully) failed to stop them.56

These debates reveal that the extent to which sections 2 and 6 were understood to apply to private individuals was contested. But amid this disagreement, a baseline consensus emerged: that sections 2 and 6 triggered when states allowed white people to commit race-based life, liberty, and property deprivations with impunity.

B. Early Caselaw Interpreting Sections 2 and 6.

Congressman Garfield’s concenrs about section 2 came to fruition in 1883, when the Supreme Court held the provision’s criminal component unconstitutional in United States v. Harris.57 As Brandwein explains, Harris is generally viewed as putting “sins of omission” outside the purview of the Fourteenth Amendment, rejecting the concept of state nonenforcement as an equal protection violation.58 But the force of that view is undermined by the fact that Harris was written by Justice William Woods, who twelve years earlier had endorsed a theory of state nonenforcement as a circuit judge in United States v. Hall.59 And indeed, Justice Woods’s problem with section 2—like Congressman Garfield’s—was that it was “not properly predicated.”60 He wrote that “[i]t applies, no matter how well the State may have performed its duty,” even when states “recognize and protect the rights of all persons.”61

Harris, then, did not “slam[] the door on future [federal] legislation” regarding “sins of omission”: it just made clear that Congress could only step in if states failed to enforce their own laws.62 Today, the civil conspiracy component of section 2 survives codified at § 1985(3), as it was not tested before the nineteenth-century Court. But if one reads a state nonenforcement requirement into it, as Congressmen Perry and Farnsworth did, the Harris problem is solved and its constitutionality with respect to private conspiracies—as a historical matter—is clear. That same logic applies to section 6, which survives codified at § 1986.63

C. Squaring the Historical Understanding of Sections 2 and 6 with Modern Cases

Though the Supreme Court has rarely spoken as to the meaning of § 1985’s civil conspiracy provision,64 the few cases interpreting it do not foreclose, and may well support, using it to remedy racial violence committed by private actors and facilitated by state nonenforcement. In Griffin v. Breckenridge, the Court held that § 1985 could be used to remedy a private conspiracy by a group of white men to commit racial violence against two Black motorists traveling on Mississippi state highways.65 Perplexingly, however, Griffin grounded its holding, not in the Fourteenth Amendment, but rather in the Thirteenth.66

From the outset, the Griffin Court struggled to explain why § 1985 contained language “similar to that of . . . the Fourteenth Amendment,”67 but also why, by its plain text, § 1985 extended to purely private conspiracies, noting that “[a] century of Fourteenth Amendment adjudication has . . . made it understandably difficult to conceive of what might constitute a deprivation of the equal protection of the laws by private persons.”68 The Court made a curious allusion to Harris, noting that “there is nothing inherent in the phrase [‘equal protection’] that requires the action working the deprivation to come from the State.”69 But instead of canvassing the enactment debates of the Klan Act and the precise language of early cases interpreting it to locate and define the concept of state nonenforcement as an equal protection violation actionable under § 1985,70 the Court made the doctrinally easier decision to characterize the conspiracy at issue as a Thirteenth Amendment violation.71 The Griffin Court then concluded that Congress could legislate under the Thirteenth Amendment to create a “statutory cause of action for Negro citizens who have been the victims of conspiratorial, racially discriminatory private action aimed at depriving them of the basic rights that the law secures to all free men.”72

For present purposes, what is most important about Griffin is not its somewhat anachronistic reasoning, but rather its result: the case permits Black plaintiffs to use § 1985 to seek damages for conspiracies to commit racial violence by white assailants, at least where that violence amounts to a denial of the “basic rights” protected by the Thirteenth Amendment.73 In a future case, a court could build on Griffin to explain that even where the deprivation of “basic rights” is not at issue, any conspiracy to commit racial violence that is facilitated by a failure of state law enforcement is independently actionable under § 1985 as an equal protection violation.74

The Supreme Court has never interpreted § 1986. But a handful of lower-court cases have followed the plain meaning of its text: “[t]o set forth a violation of § 1986, a plaintiff must first prove a violation of § 1985”; then, the plaintiff must allege that “the defendant had actual knowledge of the § 1985 conspiracy,” “the defendant had the power to prevent or aid in preventing the commission of the § 1985 violation,” “the defendant neglected or refused to prevent” the conspiracy, and “a wrongful act was committed by the conspirators.”75 In other words, § 1985 and § 1986 require different levels of culpability: Section 1985 requires, at the very least, that a defendant “be a conspirator and . . . have joined in the illegal conspiracy by at least manifesting his or her agreement with the conspiratorial plan,”76 while § 1986 “requires no such direct connection to the conspiratorial agreement” and merely attaches “liability for culpable inaction.”77 As a result, under a straightforward extension of Griffin, anyone (whether a private or state actor) who negligently fails to prevent a conspiracy to commit racial violence that denies a Black victim the basic rights protected by the Thirteenth Amendment can be held liable under § 1986. Moreover, if § 1985’s civil conspiracy provision is read to encompass private acts of racial violence that do not implicate the Thirteenth Amendment but are facilitated by state nonenforcement (thus implicating the Fourteenth Amendment), then § 1986 provides a cause of action against the state actors who failed to adequately enforce the law.

Clark v. Clabaugh,78 which Fisher describes extensively in the only article-length study of §1986 to date,79 lays out what a historically informed reading of the provision might look like in practice. Clark arose when a group of white supremacist bikers descended on Hanover, Pennsylvania to drive out an “interracial group” which “regularly congregated and socialized” in the town square.80 Despite knowing of the potential for a hostile confrontation, the Hanover Police Department sent only six officers to guard the square.81 During July 13th and 14th, 1991, the groups clashed multiple times, causing physical injuries and property damage.82 A group of Black plaintiffs who were harmed in the melee brought a claim under § 1986 against the Hanover mayor and police leadership, alleging that they had “actual knowledge” of a § 1985 conspiracy involving the bikers and failed to take action to prevent the violence that occurred.83 The Third Circuit reversed the district court’s grant of summary judgment to the municipal defendants, concluding that the plaintiffs had adequately pled a § 1986 claim.84

Clark did not discuss the constitutional basis of the alleged § 1985 conspiracy beyond noting that “[t]he plaintiffs brought this action in the district court under the Fourth and Fourteenth Amendments to the United States Constitution . . . .”85 The opinion did note, however, that the Hanover police had “failed to provide for proper training of . . . personnel to handle civil disobedience incidents,” “failed to equip police personnel with appropriate riot control equipment,” and suffered from “deficiencies in the police communication network established to coordinate police efforts.”86 Vacating the district court’s summary judgment grant, the court held that these problems could have supported a finding of pervasive state nonenforcement which permitted the bikers to conspire to descend upon the town and commit racist violence—the sort of conduct that would have violated the Equal Protection Clause as it was historically understood.87 Though the Third Circuit did not specify whether its analysis sounded in equal protection, the municipal officials’ failures to enforce the law satisfied the Fourteenth Amendment’s state action requirement. That, in turn, permitted the plaintiffs to sue the bikers directly under § 1985 for conspiring to deprive them of equal protection by committing acts of racial terrorism, activating § 1986 and facilitating a suit against the mayor and police leadership premised on mere negligence.88

What these cases illustrate is that no precedent stands in the way of embracing readings of §1985 and § 1986 that permit suits against state officials who negligently fail to enforce the law and in so doing facilitate private conspiracies of two or more persons to commit racial violence.

III. The Klan Act’s Application to Prison Litigation

One might be tempted, after considering the historical evidence presented in Part II, to ask “so what?” Constitutional law as it currently stands does not recognize the concept of nonenforcement as an equal protection violation,89 and §§ 1985 and 1986 are far from the most important tools in a twenty-first century civil rights litigator’s toolkit. Be that as it may, the history behind these provisions, and the manner in which they were understood to facilitate enforcement of the Equal Protection Clause, may have real benefits for a particular class of civil rights plaintiffs: incarcerated people.

Prison litigation offers a compelling case study for testing out a historical interpretation of the Klan Act because the racial dynamics at work in prisons bear a striking resemblance to the racial dynamics at work in the Reconstruction-era South.90 In the years following Robert E. Lee’s surrender at Appomattox, Black people in the South faced relentless acts of racial terrorism and mob violence at the hands of the Ku Klux Klan, often with tacit or express state support.91 Today, private perpetuators of racial harm do not usually employ such unabashed, all-encompassing, and violent tactics. Not usually, that is—except in prisons.

A. Prison Officials as Facilitators of Inmate-on-Inmate Racial Violence

Around the country, correctional officers routinely fail to protect Black inmates from racially motivated violence.92 Gangs are a pervasive part of contemporary prison life in America.93 A handful of these gangs, like the Aryan Brotherhood, overtly espouse white supremacy and engage in both the organized crime typical of gangs and hate crimes.94 Frequently, prison officials are aware of these gang dynamics and either purposefully place Black inmates in harm’s way or are negligent with respect to their placement. At Corcoran Prison in California, for instance, guards put Black inmates into a cell known as the “Aryan Tank,” where “they were made to face down inmates later described as ‘white supremacists.’”95 At Oklahoma City’s Kay County Detention Center in 2017, a supervising officer “ordered corrections officers serving under him to move two Black pretrial detainees . . . to a cell row containing white supremacist inmates whom [he] knew were a danger to [them].”96 The two detainees were ultimately attacked.97 And in 2021, the Washington Informer reported that “top Ku Klux Klan members in America’s prisons hold unlimited power over inmates.”98

For Black inmates, then, life in prison resembles life in the Reconstruction-era South in an important respect: just as Black people during Reconstruction faced vigilante mobs of Ku Klux Klan members that were either supported by or ignored by the state, Black inmates today face violence from white supremacist inmates, which is either facilitated or disregarded by prison officials.

B. Recognized Legal Tools for Combatting Racially Motivated Inmate-on-Inmate Prison Violence

Under civil rights law as it currently stands, inmates subjected to racially tinged private violence can sue prison officials for constitutional violations in two limited circumstances.99 First, if a guard, for example, placed a Black inmate in a yard with white supremacist inmates, and did so with the intent that the Black inmate suffer racial violence because of the placement, the inmate could sue the guard for intentional race discrimination under § 1983 (a violation of the Equal Protection Clause as the Court has always understood it). One might call this, somewhat oxymoronically, “intentional” neglect. To succeed on such a claim, the inmate would have to show that the guard acted with a discriminatory purpose.100 Given the burden of such a showing, cases proceeding on this theory are rare.

Brown v. Budz,101 a Seventh Circuit opinion from 2005, illustrates how this kind of claim could be pled. In Brown, the plaintiff, a white man, was housed in a state facility for sexually violent persons; while playing cards in an unsupervised recreation room, he was attacked by a Black resident who “had attacked other Caucasian [f]acility residents on other occasions.”102 The plaintiff sued various facility personnel, alleging that they violated the Equal Protection Clause by intentionally “failing to protect [him] from attacks by African-American residents” and “failing to investigate [the assailant’s] attacks” on him and other residents.103 The district court dismissed on the ground that the plaintiff had failed to state facts tending to show discriminatory intent, but the Seventh Circuit reversed, emphasizing “the liberal requirements of notice pleading” under the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure and concluding that the plaintiff had made out an Equal Protection claim.104 A Black plaintiff could make precisely the same kind of claim if the races in the Brown fact pattern were reversed.

Second, the injured inmate could dispense with the Equal Protection Clause and instead sue the correctional official on an Eighth Amendment theory, again under § 1983. Proceeding under the Eighth Amendment has two advantages over the “intentional neglect” theory: it does not require a showing of racial animus, and it requires only “deliberate indifference” to the inmate’s safety rather than purposeful misconduct.105 Even so, the “deliberate indifference” standard itself is difficult to satisfy. Under Farmer v. Brennan, the canonical case on this point, an inmate making an Eighth Amendment “failure to protect” claim must show: (1) that “he is incarcerated under conditions posing a substantial risk of serious harm,”106 and (2) that the official is “both . . . aware of facts from which the inference could be drawn that a substantial risk of serious harm exists” and has actually “draw[n] the inference.”107 The standard, in other words, has both an objective and a subjective component. So cases involving successful Eighth Amendment claims for the failure to protect from violence are uncommon but occasionally successful.

Nelson v. Tompkins, a recent case from the Eleventh Circuit, illustrates the extreme facts necessary for a claim like this make it past the pleadings stage.108 In Nelson, a Black man named Hatchett was charged with aggravated assault after stabbing a white store clerk, allegedly because he was angry after “watching news reports of white police officers shooting [B]lack men.”109 In custody, Hatchett mentioned the circumstances surrounding the stabbing to various jail officials; they nevertheless placed him in a cell with Nelson, a white man.110 Hatchett subsequently strangled Nelson, and Nelson’s estate brought a Fourteenth Amendment claim against various prison officials.111 The officials moved to dismiss on qualified immunity grounds, the trial court denied the motion, and the Eleventh Circuit affirmed, reasoning that “Hatchett’s underlying offense made the risk of serious harm he posed to white detainees . . . obvious” and Nelson’s estate had “provided enough evidence from which a jury could reasonably find” that the officials were “deliberately indifferent to the substantial risk of serious harm Nelson faced.”112

Lesser theories of fault do not offer viable bases for a claim against a prison official for the failure to protect against racially motivated inmate-on-inmate violence. For example, in Kingsley v. Hendrickson, the Supreme Court adopted a different Eighth Amendment test for the use of excessive force by jail officials in the pretrial context that considers only whether the force used was “objectively unreasonable” without any subjective inquiry.113 But the Court has not extended Kingsley to “failure to protect” claims based on the Eighth Amendment, or to equivalent claims brought under the Fourteenth Amendment in the pretrial context.114 Similarly, the Court has long declined to impose Eighth Amendment liability for simple negligence, reasoning that doing so would fly in the face of other Eighth Amendment precedents that require the “unnecessary and wanton infliction of pain.”115 These limitations, coupled with those imposed by the Prison Litigation Reform Act,116 mean that it is difficult—to put it mildly—for inmates to recover against prison officials who fail to protect them from inmate-on-inmate racial violence.

C. Sections 1985 and 1986: Paving the Way to a Simple Negligence Standard

Sections 1985 and 1986, coupled with the concept of state nonenforcement as an equal protection violation, offer plaintiffs who have been subjected to inmate-on-inmate racial violence a potential pathway to recovering from prison officials for simple negligence. As noted, conspiracies by gangs like the Aryan Brotherhood to assault or murder Black inmates are commonplace in prisons across America. To be sure, such conspiracies on their own are not enough to trigger civil liability under §§ 1985 or 1986, but racial violence in prisons often arises because corrections officials either deliberately or negligently place Black inmates in cells with white supremacists, leading to grisly fights and even deaths that the officials do not stop.117 On a systemic level, such actions begin to look a great deal like state nonenforcement because the culpable officials are effectively refusing to provide adequate protection to Black inmates.

It follows that if at least two inmates (say, white supremacist gang members) conspired to assault a Black inmate, the Black inmate could sue the guard(s) who placed him in danger under § 1986, alleging that the guard knew of the potential of a § 1985 conspiracy by the inmate-assailants and negligently failed to prevent it. The inmate could also potentially hold the operator of the prison liable for chronic nonenforcement. It is true that the doctrine of sovereign immunity would likely bar a § 1986 suit against a state corrections department, unless a court made the unlikely determination that Congress had abrogated sovereign immunity when it enacted § 1986.118 But if the prison in question was operated by a private prison company, the inmate could likely sue the company without the strictures of sovereign immunity.119 The same holds true if the operator of the prison was a municipality.120

Consequently, in a narrow but important class of cases, a historical understanding of §§ 1985 and 1986 might make it easier for incarcerated plaintiffs to recover against prison officials and (in some circumstances) prison operators. Section 1986, properly interpreted, creates liability for simple negligence when an official with “power to prevent or aid in preventing” a conspiracy between two or more people to commit an act of racial violence “neglects or refuses” to do so.121 Under existing law, such liability is only possible if the official has been “intentionally negligent” in choosing where to place an inmate,122 or if the official has exhibited deliberate indifference to the inmate’s placement.123 Both of these standards of fault contain subjective components that make them extremely difficult for a plaintiff to prove. Simple negligence, on the other hand, is both purely objective and easier to show.124

Conclusion

Implementing the framework described in this essay would be difficult and many open questions remain. How would a plaintiff prove the presence of chronic state nonenforcement sufficient to allege a civil conspiracy to violate the Equal Protection Clause under § 1985 and official negligence under § 1986? And how does one distinguish between mere underenforcement and actionable nonenforcement? Because “the concept [of nonenforcement] was undertheorized and unelaborated” in the Reconstruction era, there is little in the way of clear guidance in the legislative history and caselaw from the time.125 Indeed, as Part II noted, the legislators who debated the Klan Act were themselves unsure about whether, and to what extent, its provisions could reach private individuals. In addition, modern hurdles complicate the picture. The Prison Litigation Reform Act makes it challenging for prisoners to bring civil rights claims and limits the attorney’s fees available for successful suits.126 Moreover, qualified immunity applies to any § 1983 and § 1985 civil conspiracy claim against a state official and could easily be extended to § 1986 claims against such officials as well.127 On the other hand, the judiciary’s increasing hostility to qualified immunity might lead courts to refuse to extend the doctrine to new situations 128 More importantly, using § 1985 and § 1986 in the manner described in this essay would not require a radical overhaul of the Supreme Court’s more recent precedents. It would simply require the right plaintiff.

* * *

As one commentator recently argued, originalism is “our law.”129 With the Supreme Court expressing increasing interest in a historically informed conception of the Fourteenth Amendment,130 civil rights plaintiffs can use that history to their advantage. As Senator Howard said over one-hundred-fifty years ago:

Is it not time, Mr. President, that we extend to the black man, I had almost called it the poor privilege of the equal protection of the law? Ought not the time to be now passed when one measure of justice is to be meted out to a member of one caste while another and a different measure is meted out to the member of another caste, both castes being alike citizens of the United States, both bound to obey the same laws, to sustain the burdens of the same Government . . . ?131

It is time to resurrect the Equal Protection Clause. And the Ku Klux Klan Act of 1871 provides a path, though perhaps partially concealed by the weeds of history, through which to implement the Clause’s guarantees. We need only accept its invitation to do so.

Continue reading Resurrecting the Equal Protection Clause Through the Ku Klux Klan Act of 1871

The Problems with Using the Criminal Legal System to Fight the Criminal Legal System

By: Kevin Trahan

Former Dallas police officer Amber Guyger was convicted of murder on Tuesday and sentenced to 10 years in prison, just over a year after shooting and killing a 26-year-old black man named Botham Jean sitting in his apartment. Guyger lived in the same apartment complex as Jean, and after she walked into Jean’s apartment and shot him, unprovoked, she claimed she thought she was entering her own apartment and he had broken in.

The shooting rightfully provoked outrage, as it is among the most heinous instances of police killing unarmed black men across the country. At trial, Guyger testified that she was returning from a long shift, accidentally went to the wrong floor of the apartment complex, walked in, and fired within seconds upon seeing a “silhouetted person” approach her at a “fast-paced” walk.[1] It is plausible that Guyger walked into the wrong apartment by accident, but her subsequent actions were inexcusable. Jean was unarmed, and rather than leave or attempt to diffuse the situation, her first reaction was to shoot. The story fit a familiar pattern: a police officer claiming they were “scared”  and using that as an excuse to shoot an unarmed black man who posed no immediate threat—and, in most instances, no threat at all. Such was the case in the killings of Jean, Michael Brown, Terence Crutcher, Laquan McDonald, Philando Castile, Tamir Rice, Stephon Clark, and countless others.

This fear of black male bodies has been used as justification for their killings again and again. In a rare instance, a Dallas jury made clear it wouldn’t accept this excuse.

The epidemic of police violence is undeniable. This year alone, 660 people have been shot and killed by police.[2] 992 people were killed by police in 2018. As the shootings have gained more attention, particularly since the killing of Michael Brown in Ferguson, Missouri, in 2014, activists have called for accountability. The rise of the Black Lives Matter movement has drawn wide public attention to the problem, and to the institutionalized racism present in law enforcement and prosecutors’ offices.[3] The movement’s influence has provided hope that finally, there will be accountability for a system that consistently violates the rights of people of color and the poor. The question we are left with is what does accountability looks like.

In the death of Botham Jean, accountability has meant the prosecution of Guyger. The focus on prosecuting Guyger as an expression of accountability is understandable. The criminal legal system has engrained in Americans that criminal punishment is the only legitimate way to express disapproval of violence.

However, this approach to accountability does nothing to address the substantive root causes behind why the violence occurred. It is, in many ways, a cop-out: it allows the unjust criminal legal system to capitalize off of legitimate anger by the public and place blame on the perpetrator of violence, rather than the system itself. The system deserves the majority of the blame, but in the prosecution of Guyger, the system and its supporters have effectively shifted the blame to a single actor—avoiding accountability and ensuring more injustices are sure to come. Ta-Nehisi Coates aptly explained the trouble with a prosecutorial approach to violence in his criticism of the Obama Justice Department’s decision to seek the death penalty against Dylann Roof, a white supremacist who murdered nine members of a black church in Charleston, South Carolina:

The hammer of criminal justice is the preferred tool of a society that has run out of ideas. In this sense, Roof is little more than a human sacrifice to The Gods of Doing Nothing. Leave aside actual substantive policy. In a country where unapologetic slaveholders and regressive white supremacists still, at this late date, adorn our state capitals and our highest institutions of learning, it is bizarre to kill a man who acted in their spirit. And killing Roof, like the business of the capital punishment itself, ensures that innocent people will be executed. The need to extract vengeance cannot always be exact. It is all but certain that a disproportionate number of those who pay for this lack of precision will not look like Dylann Roof.[4]

One need not feel sympathy for Guyger to recognize that she is a useful scapegoat for a system of law enforcement and prosecution that will happily throw one it its own to “The Gods of Doing Nothing” in order to avoid systemic change. In the time since Guyger killed Jean just one year ago, Texas police officers have killed 84 people. Justice for Jean, and justice for all, should be focused on accountability for that system.

There are far better responses to Jean’s killing than those that resort to the criminal legal system. The most obvious solution is to scale back and eventually abolish what has essentially become an occupying force in minority communities.

The activism of Critical Resistance in Oakland, California, provides a good example of how to respond to police killings with systemic solutions. When San Francisco police killed a 19-year-old undocumented resident named Adolfo Delgado, firing 99 shots at him while he hid to avoid deportation, the organization responded with a simple message: “to stop police murders, abolish the police.”[5]

The title is provocative, but the group listed concrete demands:

The violence of policing must be addressed by eliminating gang injunctions, defunding police departments, reducing the number of cops patrolling our streets, stripping the power of police officers’ associations, ending police militarization programs such as Urban Shield, and rejecting the purchase of new weapons or surveillance technology. It is efforts such as these that will reduce the police’s ability to harass, harm, and kill our community members, and ultimately, bring us closer to a vision where our communities live free from state violence.

Shootings in other communities have prompted similar responses, with actual results. For example, a recent study found that Austin, Texas, has the highest number of police killings per capital following mental health calls.[6] In a particularly jarring incident before the study was released, an Austin police officer shot and killed a naked, unarmed black teenager who was exhibiting symptoms of a mental health crisis.[7] The officer was fired, though not criminally indicted. Rather, under pressure from local activists Austin’s city council has invested in a program that sends mental health professionals, rather than police, to attend to mental health calls.[8] Of course, there is still a long way to go in Austin, where the city council just approved the police force’s request to increase in size.[9] However, activists in the city have shown that they can be successful in calling for a type of accountability that reshapes at least part of the system.

Prosecuting Amber Guyger will not change the negative impact the Dallas police have on the poor and communities of color. However, fighting for systemic change that fundamentally alters the system, such as has been done in Austin and Oakland, would provide true justice for Jean and residents of Dallas.

Guyger rightfully outraged activists during her testimony, because despite showing little (or really any) remorse after killing Jean, she showed emotion on stage when faced with a murder charge. The reaction—anger displayed not at the killing, but at a loss of privilege she never expected to lose—was repulsive to many.

As activist Elisabeth Epps noted following Guyger’s testimony: “Not 1 real teardrop in 2 mins of fake hiccups. She can’t even summon the weaponized white tears that usually accompany white fragility. Repulsive. Justice is not sending #BothamJean’s racist killer #AmberGuyger to a cage. Justice would be abolishing the police.”[10]

A common response to those in favor of criminal prosecution of Guyger and other officers is why not both?

On an emotional level, this is a fair response. Police officers are so rarely prosecuted, or even indicted, for their violence—despite that, in most cases, grand juries will “indict a ham sandwich”—it can feel like the system is finally working against the very people it is designed to work for. And because healing is important in response to violence, any future must employ restorative justice mechanisms that bring together victims and offenders to determine how the offender can provide some sort of healing.

It was clear that Jean’s family was open to some sort of restorative mechanism beyond, or in some cases in place of, the criminal legal system. Jean’s brother, Brandt Jean, said that he didn’t want Guyger to go to jail,[11] while his mother stated in a press conference that, “[t]here’s much more that needs to be done by the city of Dallas. The corruption that we saw during this process must stop.”[12] (It is important to note that Brandt Jean’s expression of forgiveness should not be used as an excuse to do nothing about systemic abuses.[13])

Unfortunately, the system we have is not designed to be restorative—rather, it is vengeance-driven. And the problem with embracing a vengeance-driven system is that, as Coates noted, “the need to extract vengeance cannot always be exact.”

Prosecuting Guyger legitimizes a racist system. It allows law enforcement to claim to care about racism in the system while not actually fixing anything. It provides plausible deniability when the system inevitably retreats to its racist, classist ways—victimizing mostly communities of color and the poor with over-policing and over-prosecution. The same prosecutors who jailed Guyger will use their power and newfound legitimacy to jail far more poor people and people of color than perpetrators of racist violence.

Even portions of the trial itself have legitimized improper prosecutorial tactics. Self-proclaimed racial justice advocates were cheerleaders for the slut-shaming of Guyger, who it was revealed was having a relationship with her patrol partner.[14] Other activists called out Gugyer for having sex days after the shooting, following a pattern of prosecutors using charged language to ignore the fact that people have tremendously different reactions to trauma in different situations.

Many activists regard Guyger’s prison sentence as a win. She is now subject to a punishment that police officers hardly ever see—a punishment typically endured by communities like Botham Jean’s.

But even now that Guyger is locked up, there will be no more justice than there was the day before. The police will still occupy communities of color and the poor, bombarding them with expressions of state violence. The criminal legal system will have an example of the time it worked to “fight racism,” only to lock up more black and brown people in the future.

As prison abolitionist Mariame Kaba wrote in response to Guyger’s verdict, “Abolition demands no cages for anyone. It’s really that simple and that complex. Prison in the meantime is not abolitionist.”[15]

It is human nature to want accountability for a senseless killing. And communities of color and the poor have dealt with a far harsher and more unjust version of accountability than any police officer. But true accountability starts with finally creating structural change that scales back and eventually abolishes the racist, classist occupying force that is the police and the prison system. It will never come if we are willing to legitimize the carceral system just to extract vengeance in the meantime.

[1] Tanya Ballard Brown, ‘I Hate Myself,’ Former Dallas Police Officer Who Killed Neighbor Tells Jurors, NPR (Sept. 27, 2019), https://www.npr.org/2019/09/27/765122240/i-hate-myself-former-dallas-police-officer-tells-jurors-during-murder-trial.

[2] Fatal Force, Wash. Post (last visited Sept. 29, 2019), https://www.washingtonpost.com/graphics/2019/national/police-shootings-2019/.

[3] Frank Leon Roberts, How Black Lives Matter Changed the Way Americans Fight for Freedom, ACLU (Jul. 13, 2018), https://www.aclu.org/blog/racial-justice/race-and-criminal-justice/how-black-lives-matter-changed-way-americans-fight.

[4] Ta-Nehisi Coates, Killing Dylann Roof, Atlantic (May 26, 2016), https://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2016/05/dylann-roof-death-penalty/484274/.

[5] To Stop Police Murders, Abolish the Police, Critical Resistance (Mar. 19, 2018), http://criticalresistance.org/to-stop-police-murders-abolish-the-police/.

[6] Heather Osbourne, Austin Leads in Police Shootings During Mental Health Calls, Study Finds, Austin Am.-Statesman (Sept. 24, 2019), https://www.statesman.com/news/20190924/austin-leads-in-police-shootings-during-mental-health-calls-study-finds.

[7] Philip Jankowski, Austin Police Fire Officer Who Fatally Shot Naked Teen David Joseph, Austin Am.-Statesman (Sept. 27, 2018), https://www.statesman.com/NEWS/20160922/Austin-police-fire-officer-who-fatally-shot-naked-teen-David-Joseph.

[8] Yoojin Cho, Austin Approves Spending Millions on Improving Mental Health Call Response, KXAN (Sept. 11, 2019), https://www.kxan.com/news/local/austin/city-of-austin-budget-makes-effort-to-focus-on-mental-health-improvements/.

[9] Philip Jankowski, Austin City Council Approves Record $4.2 Billion Budget, Austin Am.-Statesman (Sept. 10, 2019), https://www.statesman.com/news/20190910/austin-city-council-approves-record-42-billion-budget.

[10] Elizabeth epps is tired. (@elisabeth), Twitter (Sept. 27, 2019, 11:46 AM CT), https://twitter.com/elisabeth/status/1177625470273146880.

[11] ABC News (@ABC), Twitter (Oct. 2, 2019, 4:42 PM CT), https://twitter.com/ABC/status/1179511887500726272.

[12] Marjorie Owens, ‘There’s Gotta be a Better Day,’ Says Botham Jean’s Mother after Amber Guyger Sentencing, WFAA (Oct. 2, 2019), https://www.wfaa.com/article/news/special-reports/botham-jean/theres-gotta-be-a-better-day-says-botham-jeans-mother-after-amber-guyger-sentencing.

[13] Jemar Tisby, White Christians, Do Not Cheapen the Hug and Message of Forgiveness from Botham Jean’s Brother, Wash. Post (Oct. 3, 2019, 11:36 AM CT), https://www.washingtonpost.com/religion/2019/10/03/white-christians-do-not-cheapen-hug-message-forgiveness-botham-jeans-brother.

[14] Cory Provost (@coryprovost), Twitter (Sept. 27, 2019, 11:26 AM CT), https://twitter.com/coryprovost/status/1177620450979004417.

[15] #FreeTondalao (@prisonculture), Twitter (Oct. 1, 2019, 4:38 PM CT), https://twitter.com/prisonculture/status/1179148524795154433.